Dialectical
and Historical Materialism
By Joseph Stalin
Dialectical materialism is the world outlook of the
Marxist-Leninist party. It is called dialectical materialism because its
approach to the phenomena of nature, its method of studying and apprehending
them, is dialectical, while its interpretation of the phenomena of
nature, its conception of these phenomena, its theory, is materialistic.
Historical materialism is the extension of the
principles of dialectical materialism to the study of social life, an
application of the principles of dialectical materialism to the phenomena of
the life of society, to the study of society and its history.
When describing their dialectical method, Marx and
Engels usually refer to Hegel as the philosopher who formulated the main
features of dialectics. This, however, does not mean that the dialectics of
Marx and Engels is identical with the dialectics of Hegel. As a matter of fact,
Marx and Engels took from the Hegelian dialectics only its “rational kernel,” casting
aside its idealistic shell, and developed it further so as to lend it a modern
scientific form.
“My dialectic method,” says Marx, “is fundamentally
not only different from the Hegelian, but is its direct opposite. To Hegel, the
process of thinking, which, under the name of ‘the Idea,’ he even transforms
into an independent subject, is the demiurge (creator) of the real world, and
the real world is only the external, phenomenal form of ‘the Idea.’ With me, on
the contrary, the ideal is nothing else than the material world reflected by
the human mind, and translated into forms of thought.” (Karl Marx, Capital,
Vol. I, p. xxx, International Publishers, 1939.)
When describing their materialism, Marx and Engels
usually refer to Feuerbach as the philosopher who restored materialism to its
rights. This, however, does not mean that the materialism of Marx and Engels is
identical with Feuerbach’s materialism. As a matter of fact, Marx and Engels
took from Feuerbach’s materialism its “inner kernel,” developed it into a
scientific-philosophical theory of materialism and cast aside its idealistic
and religious-ethical encumbrances. We know that Feuerbach, although he was
fundamentally a materialist, objected to the name materialism. Engels more than
once declared that “in spite of the materialist foundation, Feuerbach remained
bound by the traditional idealist fetters,” and that “the real idealism of
Feuerbach becomes evident as soon as we come to his philosophy of religion and
ethics.” (Karl Marx, Selected Works, Vol. I, pp. 439, 442.)
Dialectics comes from the Greek dialego, to
discourse, to debate. In ancient times dialectics was the art of arriving at
the truth by disclosing the contradictions in the argument of an opponent and
overcoming these contradictions. There were philosophers in ancient times who
believed that the disclosure of contradictions in thought and the clash of
opposite opinions was the best method of arriving at the truth. This
dialectical method of thought, later extended to the phenomena of nature,
developed into the dialectical method of apprehending nature, which regards the
phenomena of nature as being in constant movement and undergoing constant
change, and the development of nature as the result of the development of the
contradictions in nature, as the result of the interaction of opposed forces in
nature.
In its essence, dialectics is the direct opposite of
metaphysics.
1) The principal features of the Marxist dialectical
method are as follows:
a) Contrary to metaphysics, dialectics does not regard
nature as an accidental agglomeration of things, of phenomena, unconnected
with, isolated from, and independent of, each other, but as a connected and
integral whole, in which things, phenomena, are organically connected with,
dependent on, and determined by, each other.
The dialectical method therefore holds that no
phenomenon in nature can be understood if taken by itself, isolated from
surrounding phenomena, inasmuch as any phenomenon in any realm of nature may
become meaningless to us if it is not considered in connection with the
surrounding conditions, but divorced from them; and that, vice versa, any
phenomenon can be understood and explained if considered in its inseparable
connection with surrounding phenomena, as one conditioned by surrounding
phenomena.
b) Contrary to metaphysics, dialectics holds that
nature is not a state of rest and immobility, stagnation and immutability, but
a state of continuous movement and change, of continuous renewal and
development, where something is always arising and developing, and something
always disintegrating and dying away.
The dialectical method therefore requires that
phenomena should be considered not only from the standpoint of their
interconnection and interdependence, but also from the standpoint of their
movement, their change, their development, their coming into being and going
out of being.
The dialectical method regards as important primarily
not that which at the given moment seems to be durable and yet is already
beginning to die away, but that which is arising and developing, even though at
the given moment it may appear to be not durable, for the dialectical method
considers invincible only that which is arising and developing.
“All nature,” says Engels, “from the smallest thing to
the biggest, from a grain of sand to the sun, from the protista (the primary
living cell – Ed.) to man, is in a constant state of coming into being
and going out of being, in a constant flux, in a ceaseless state of movement
and change.” (F. Engels, Dialectics of Nature.)
Therefore, dialectics, Engels says, “takes things and
their perceptual images essentially in their inter-connection, in their
concatenation, in their movement, in their rise and disappearance.” (Ibid.)
c) Contrary to metaphysics, dialectics does not regard
the process of development as a simple process of growth, where quantitative
changes do not lead to qualitative changes, but as a development which passes
from insignificant and imperceptible quantitative changes to open, fundamental
changes, to qualitative changes; a development in which the qualitative changes
occur not gradually, but rapidly and abruptly, taking the form of a leap from
one state to another; they occur not accidentally but as the natural result of
an accumulation of imperceptible and gradual quantitative changes.
The dialectical method therefore holds that the
process of development should be understood not as movement in a circle, not as
a simple repetition of what has already occurred, but as an onward and upward
movement, as a transition from an old qualitative state to a new qualitative
state, as a development from the simple to the complex, from the lower to the
higher:
“Nature,” says Engels, “is the test of dialectics, and
it must be said for modern natural science that it has furnished extremely rich
and daily increasing materials for this test, and has thus proved that in the
last analysis nature’s process is dialectical and not metaphysical, that it
does not move in an eternally uniform and constantly repeated circle, but passes
through a real history. Here prime mention should be made of Darwin, who dealt
a severe blow to the metaphysical conception of nature by proving that the
organic world of today, plants and animals, and consequently man too, is all a
product of a process of development that has been in progress for millions of
years.” (F. Engels, Anti-Dühring.)
Describing dialectical development as a transition
from quantitative changes to qualitative changes, Engels says:
“In physics... every change is a passing of quantity
into quality, as a result of quantitative change of some form of movement
either inherent in a body or imparted to it. For example, the temperature of
water has at first no effect on its liquid state; but as the temperature of
liquid water rises or falls, a moment arrives when this state of cohesion
changes and the water is converted in one case into steam and in the other into
ice.... A definite minimum current is required to make a platinum wire glow; every
metal has its melting temperature; every liquid has a definite freezing point
and boiling point at a given pressure, as far as we are able with the means at
our disposal to attain the required temperatures; finally, every gas has its
critical point at which, by proper pressure and cooling, it can be converted
into a liquid state.... What are known as the constants of physics (the point
at which one state passes into another – Ed.) are in most cases nothing
but designations for the nodal points at which a quantitative (change) increase
or decrease of movement causes a qualitative change in the state of the given
body, and at which, consequently, quantity is transformed into quality.” (Dialectics
of Nature?)
Passing to chemistry, Engels continues:
“Chemistry may be called the science of the
qualitative changes which take place in bodies as the effect of changes of
quantitative composition. This was already known to Hegel.... Take oxygen: if
the molecule contains three atoms instead of the customary two, we get ozone, a
body definitely distinct in odour and reaction from ordinary oxygen. And what
shall we say of the different proportions in which oxygen combines with
nitrogen or sulphur, and each of which produces a body qualitatively different
from all other bodies!” (Ibid.)
Finally, criticizing Dühring, who scolded Hegel for
all he was worth, but surreptitiously borrowed from him the well-known thesis
that the transition from the insentient world to the sentient world, from the
kingdom of inorganic matter to the kingdom of organic life, is a leap to a new
state, Engels says:
“This is precisely the Hegelian nodal line of measure
relations, in which, at certain definite nodal points, the purely quantitative
increase or decrease gives rise to a qualitative leap for example, in
the case of water which is heated or cooled, where boiling-point and
freezing-point are the nodes at which – under normal pressure – the leap to a
new aggregate state takes place, and where consequently quantity is transformed
into quality.” (F. Engels, Anti-Dühring.)
d) Contrary to metaphysics, dialectics holds that
internal contradictions are inherent in all things and phenomena of nature, for
they all have their negative and positive sides, a past and a future, something
dying away and something developing; and that the struggle between these
opposites, the struggle between the old and the new, between that which is
dying away and that which is being born, between that which is disappearing and
that which is developing, constitutes the internal content of the process of
development, the internal content of the transformation of quantitative changes
into qualitative changes.
The dialectical method therefore holds that the
process of development from the lower to the higher takes place not as a
harmonious unfolding of phenomena, but as a disclosure of the contradictions
inherent in things and phenomena, as a “struggle” of opposite tendencies which
operate on the basis of these contradictions.
“In its proper meaning,” Lenin says, “dialectics is
the study of the contradiction within the very essence of things.”
(Lenin, Philosophical Notebooks, Russ. ed., p. 263.)
And further:
“Development is the ‘struggle’ of opposites.” (Lenin, Selected
Works, Vol. XI, pp. 81-2.)
Such, in brief, are the principal features of the
Marxist dialectical method.
It is easy to understand how immensely important is
the extension of the principles of the dialectical method to the study of
social life and the history of society, and how immensely important is the
application of these principles to the history of society and to the practical
activities of the party of the proletariat.
If there are no isolated phenomena in the world, if
all phenomena are interconnected and interdependent, then it is clear that
every social system and every social movement in history must be evaluated not
from the standpoint of “eternal justice” or some other preconceived idea, as is
not infrequently done by historians, but from the standpoint of the conditions
which gave rise to that system or that social movement and with which they are
connected.
The slave system would be senseless, stupid and
unnatural under modern conditions. But under the conditions of a disintegrating
primitive communal system, the slave system is a quite understandable and
natural phenomenon, since it represents an advance on the primitive communal
system.
The demand for a bourgeois-democratic republic when
tsardom and bourgeois society existed, as, let us say, in Russia in 1905, was a
quite understandable, proper and revolutionary demand, for at that time a
bourgeois republic would have meant a step forward. But now, under the
conditions of the U.S.S.R., the demand for a bourgeois-democratic republic
would be a meaningless and counter-revolutionary demand, for a bourgeois
republic would be a retrograde step compared with the Soviet republic.
Everything depends on the conditions, time and place.
It is clear that without such a historical
approach to social phenomena, the existence and development of the science of
history is impossible, for only such an approach saves the science of history
from becoming a jumble of accidents and an agglomeration of most absurd
mistakes.
Further, if the world is in a state of constant
movement and development, if the dying away of the old and the upgrowth of the
new is a law of development, then it is clear that there can be no “immutable”
social systems, no “eternal principles” of private property and exploitation,
no “eternal ideas” of the subjugation of the peasant to the landlord, of the
worker to the capitalist.
Hence the capitalist system can be replaced by the
Socialist system, just as at one time the feudal system was replaced by the
capitalist system.
Hence we must not base our orientation on the strata
of society which are no longer developing, even though they at present
constitute the predominant force, but on those strata which are developing and
have a future before them, even though they at present do not constitute the
predominant force.
In the eighties of the past century, in the period of
the struggle between the Marxists and the Narodniks, the proletariat in Russia
constituted an insignificant minority of the population, whereas the individual
peasants constituted the vast majority of the population. But the proletariat
was developing as a class, whereas the peasantry as a class was disintegrating.
And just because the proletariat was developing as a class the Marxists based
their orientation on the proletariat. And they were not mistaken, for, as we
know, the proletariat subsequently grew from an insignificant force into a
first-rate historical and political force.
Hence, in order not to err in policy, one must look
forward, not backward.
Further, if the passing of slow quantitative changes
into rapid and abrupt qualitative changes is a law of development, then it is
clear that revolutions made by oppressed classes are a quite natural and
inevitable phenomenon.
Hence the transition from capitalism to Socialism and
the liberation of the working class from the yoke of capitalism cannot be
effected by slow changes, by reforms, but only by a qualitative change of the
capitalist system, by revolution.
Hence, in order not to err in policy, one must be a
revolutionary, not a reformist.
Further, if development proceeds by way of the disclosure
of internal contradictions, by way of collisions between opposite forces on the
basis of these contradictions and so as to overcome these contradictions, then
it is clear that the class struggle of the proletariat is a quite natural and
inevitable phenomenon.
Hence we must not cover up the contradictions of the
capitalist system, but disclose and unravel them; we must not try to check the
class struggle but carry it to its conclusion.
Hence, in order not to err in
policy, one must pursue an uncompromising proletarian class policy, not a
reformist policy of harmony of the interests of the proletariat and the
bourgeoisie, not a compromisers’ policy of “the growing of capitalism into
Socialism.”
Such is the Marxist dialectical method when applied to
social life, to the history of society.
As to Marxist philosophical materialism, it is
fundamentally the direct opposite of philosophical idealism.
2) The principal features of Marxist philosophical materialism
are as follows:
a) Contrary to idealism, which regards the world as
the embodiment of an “absolute idea,” a “universal spirit,” “consciousness,”
Marx’s philosophical materialism holds that the world is by its very nature material,
that the multifold phenomena of the world constitute different forms of matter
in motion, that interconnection and interdependence of phenomena, as
established by the dialectical method, are a law of the development of moving
matter, and that the world develops in accordance with the laws of movement of
matter and stands in no need of a “universal spirit.”
“The materialist world outlook,” says Engels, “is
simply the conception of nature as it is, without any reservations.” (MS of Ludwig
Feuerbach.)
Speaking of the materialist views of the ancient
philosopher Heraclitus, who held that “the world, the all in one, was not
created by any god or any man, but was, is and ever will be a living flame,
systematically flaring up and systematically dying down,” Lenin comments: “A
very good exposition of the rudiments of dialectical materialism.” (Lenin, Philosophical
Notebooks, Russ. ed., p. 318.)
b) Contrary to idealism, which asserts that only our
mind really exists, and that the material world, being, nature, exists only in
our mind, in our sensations, ideas and perceptions, the Marxist materialist
philosophy holds that matter, nature, being, is an objective reality existing
outside and independent of our mind; that matter is primary, since it is the
source of sensations, ideas, mind, and that mind is secondary, derivative,
since it is a reflection of matter, a reflection of being; that thought is a
product of matter which in its development has reached a high degree of
perfection, namely, of the brain, and the brain is the organ of thought; and
that therefore one cannot separate thought from matter without committing a
grave error. Engels says:
“The question of the relation of thinking to being,
the relation of spirit to nature is the paramount question of the whole of
philosophy.... The answers which the philosophers gave to this question split
them into two great camps. Those who asserted the primacy of spirit to
nature... comprised the camp of idealism. The others, who regarded
nature as primary, belong to the various schools of materialism.” (Karl Marx, Selected
Works, Vol. I, pp. 430-31.)
And further:
“The material, sensuously perceptible world to which
we ourselves belong is the only reality.... Our consciousness and thinking,
however supra-sensuous they may seem, are the product of a material, bodily
organ, the brain. Matter is not a product of mind, but mind itself is merely
the highest product of matter.” (Ibid., p. 435.) Concerning the question
of matter and thought, Marx says:
“It is impossible to separate thought from matter that
thinks. Matter is the subject of all changes.” (Ibid., p. 397.)
Describing the Marxist philosophy of materialism,
Lenin says:
“Materialism in general recognizes objectively real
being (matter) as independent of consciousness, sensation, experience....
Consciousness is only the reflection of being, at best, an approximately true
(adequate, ideally exact) reflection of it.” (Lenin, Selected Works, Vol. XI, p. 378.)
And further:
(a) “Matter is that which, acting upon our
sense-organs, produces sensation; matter is the objective reality given to us
in sensation.... Matter, nature, being, the physical – is primary, and spirit,
consciousness, sensation, the psychical – is secondary.” (Ibid.., pp.
208, 209.)
(b) “The world picture is a picture of how matter
moves and of how ‘matter thinks.’“ (Ibid.., p. 403.)
(c) “The brain is the organ of thought.” (Ibid..,
p. 125.)
c) Contrary to idealism, which denies the possibility
of knowing the world and its laws, which does not believe in the authenticity
of our knowledge, does not recognize objective truth, and holds that the world
is full of “things-in-themselves” that can never be known to science, Marxist
philosophical materialism holds that the world and its laws are fully knowable,
that our knowledge of the laws of nature, tested by experiment and practice, is
authentic knowledge having the validity of objective truth, and that there are
no things in the world which are unknowable, but only things which are still
not known, but which will be disclosed and made known by the efforts of science
and practice.
Criticizing the thesis of Kant and other idealists
that the world is unknowable and that there are “things-in-themselves” which
are unknowable, and defending the well-known materialist thesis that our
knowledge is authentic knowledge, Engels writes:
“The most telling refutation of this as of all other
philosophical fancies is practice, viz., experiment and industry. If we are
able to prove the correctness of our conception of a natural process by making
it ourselves, bringing it into being out of its conditions and using it for our
own purposes into the bargain, then there is an end of the Kantian
‘thing-in-itself.’ The chemical substances produced in the bodies of plants and
animals remained such ‘things-in-themselves’ until organic chemistry began to
produce them one after another, whereupon the ‘thing-in-itself’ became a thing
for us, as for instance, alizarin, the colouring matter of the madder, which we
no longer trouble to grow in the madder roots in the field, but produce much
more cheaply and simply from coal tar. For three hundred years the Copernican
solar system was a hypothesis, with a hundred, a thousand or ten thousand
chances to one in its favour, but still always a hypothesis. But when
Leverrier, by means of the data provided by this system, not only deduced the
necessity of the existence of an unknown planet, but also calculated the
position in the heavens which this planet must necessarily occupy, and when
Galle really found this planet, the Copernican system was proved.” (Karl Marx, Selected
Works, Vol. I, pp. 432-33.)
Accusing Bogdanov, Bazarov, Yushkevich and the other
followers of Mach of fideism, and defending the well-known materialist thesis
that our scientific knowledge of the laws of nature is authentic knowledge, and
that the laws of science represent objective truth, Lenin says:
“Contemporary fideism does not at all reject science;
all it rejects is the ‘exaggerated claims’ of science, to wit, its claim to
objective truth. If objective truth exists (as the materialists think), if
natural science, reflecting the outer world in human ‘experience,’ is alone
capable of giving us objective truth, then all fideism is absolutely refuted.”
(Lenin, Selected Works, Vol. XI, p. 189.)
Such, in brief, are the characteristic features of the
Marxist philosophical materialism.
It is easy to understand how immensely important is
the extension of the principles of philosophical materialism to the study of
social life, of the history of society, and how immensely important is the
application of these principles to the history of society and to the practical
activities of the party of the proletariat.
If the connection between the phenomena of nature and
their interdependence are laws of the development of nature, it follows, too,
that the connection and interdependence of the phenomena of social life are
laws of the development of society, and not something accidental.
Hence social life, the history of society, ceases to
be an agglomeration of “accidents,” and becomes the history of the development
of society according to regular laws, and the study of the history of society
becomes a science.
Hence the practical activity of the party of the
proletariat must not be based on the good wishes of “outstanding individuals,”
not on the dictates of “reason,” “universal morals,” etc., but on the laws of
development of society and on the study of these laws.
Further, if the world is knowable and our knowledge of
the laws of development of nature is authentic knowledge, having the validity
of objective truth, it follows that social life, the development of society, is
also knowable, and that the data of science regarding the laws of development
of society are authentic data having the validity of objective truths.
Hence the science of the history of society, despite
all the complexity of the phenomena of social life, can become as precise a
science as, let us say, biology, and capable of making use of the laws of
development of society for practical purposes.
Hence the party of the proletariat should not guide
itself in its practical activity by casual motives, but by the laws of
development of society, and by practical deductions from these laws.
Hence Socialism is converted from a dream of a better
future for humanity into a science.
Hence the bond between science and practical activity,
between theory and practice, their unity, should be the guiding star of the
party of the proletariat.
Further, if nature, being, the material world, is
primary, and mind, thought, is secondary, derivative; if the material world
represents objective reality existing independently of the mind of men, while
the mind is a reflection of this objective reality, it follows that the
material life of society, its being, is also primary, and its spiritual life
secondary, derivative, and that the material life of society is an objective
reality existing independently of the will of men, while the spiritual life of
society is a reflection of this objective reality, a reflection of being.
Hence the source of formation of the spiritual life of
society, the origin of social ideas, social theories, political views and
political institutions, should not be sought for in the ideas, theories, views
and political institutions themselves, but in the conditions of the material
life of society, in social being, of which these ideas, theories, views, etc.,
are the reflection.
Hence, if in different periods of the history of
society different social ideas, theories, views and political institutions are
to be observed; if under the slave system we encounter certain social ideas,
theories, views and political institutions, under feudalism others, and under
capitalism others still, this is not to be explained by the “nature,” the
“properties” of the ideas, theories, views and political institutions
themselves but by the different conditions of the material life of society at
different periods of social development.
Whatever is the being of a society, whatever are the
conditions of material life of a society, such are the ideas, theories,
political views and political institutions of that society.
In this connection, Marx says:
“It is not the consciousness of men that determines
their being, but, on the contrary, their social being that determines their
consciousness.” (Karl Marx, Selected Works, Vol. I, p. 356.)
Hence, in order not to err in policy, in order not to
find itself in the position of idle dreamers, the party of the proletariat must
not base its activities on abstract “principles of human reason,” but on the
concrete conditions of the material life of society, as the determining force
of social development; not on the good wishes of “great men,” but on the real
needs of development of the material life of society.
The fall of the utopians, including the Narodniks,
Anarchists and Socialist-Revolutionaries, was due, among other things, to the
fact that they did not recognize the primary role which the conditions of the
material life of society play in the development of society, and, sinking to
idealism, did not base their practical activities on the needs of the
development of the material life of society, but, independently of and in spite
of these needs, on “ideal plans” and “all-embracing projects” divorced from the
real life of society.
The strength and vitality of Marxism-Leninism lie in
the fact that it does base its practical activity on the needs of the
development of the material life of society and never divorces itself from the
real life of society.
It does not follow from Marx’s words, however, that
social ideas, theories, political views and political institutions are of no
significance in the life of society, that they do not reciprocally affect
social being, the development of the material conditions of the life of
society. We have been speaking so far of the origin of social ideas,
theories, views and political institutions, of the way they arise, of
the fact that the spiritual life of society is a reflection of the conditions
of its material life. As regards the significance of social ideas,
theories, views and political institutions, as regards their role in history,
historical materialism, far from denying them, stresses the role and importance
of these factors in the life of society, in its history.
There are different kinds of social ideas and
theories. There are old ideas and theories which have outlived their day and
which serve the interests of the moribund forces of society. Their significance
lies in the fact that they hamper the development, the progress of society.
Then there are new and advanced ideas and theories which serve the interests of
the advanced forces of society. Their significance lies in the fact that they
facilitate the development, the progress of society; and their significance is
the greater the more accurately they reflect the needs of development of the
material life of society.
New social ideas and theories arise only after the
development of the material life of society has set new tasks before society.
But once they have arisen they become a most potent force which facilitates the
carrying out of the new tasks set by the development of the material life of
society, a force which facilitates the progress of society. It is precisely
here that the tremendous organizing, mobilizing and transforming value of new
ideas, new theories, new political views and new political institutions manifests
itself. New social ideas and theories arise precisely because they are
necessary to society, because it is impossible to carry out the urgent
tasks of development of the material life of society without their organizing,
mobilizing and transforming action. Arising out of the new tasks set by the
development of the material life of society, the new social ideas and theories
force their way through, become the possession of the masses, mobilize and
organize them against the moribund forces of society, and thus facilitate the
overthrow of these forces which hamper the development of the material life of
society.
Thus social ideas, theories and political
institutions, having arisen on the basis of the urgent tasks of the development
of the material life of society, the development of social being, themselves
then react upon social being, upon the material life of society, creating the
conditions necessary for completely carrying out the urgent tasks of the
material life of society, and for rendering its further development possible.
In this connection, Marx says:
“Theory becomes a material force as soon as it has
gripped the masses.” (Zur Kritik der Hegelschen Rechtsphilosophie.)
Hence, in order to be able to influence the conditions
of material life of society and to accelerate their development and their
improvement, the party of the proletariat must rely upon such a social theory,
such a social idea as correctly reflects the needs of development of the
material life of society, and which is therefore capable of setting into motion
broad masses of the people and of mobilizing them and organizing them into a
great army of the proletarian party, prepared to smash the reactionary forces
and to clear the way for the advanced forces of society.
The fall of the “Economists” and Mensheviks was due
among other things to the fact that they did not recognize the mobilizing,
organizing and transforming role of advanced theory, of advanced ideas and,
sinking to vulgar materialism, reduced the role of these factors almost to
nothing, thus condemning the Party to passivity and inanition.
The strength and vitality of Marxism-Leninism are
derived from the fact that it relies upon an advanced theory which correctly
reflects the needs of development of the material life of society, that it
elevates theory to a proper level, and that it deems it its duty to utilize
every ounce of the mobilizing, organizing and transforming power of this
theory.
That is the answer historical materialism gives to the
question of the relation between social being and social consciousness, between
the conditions of development of material life and the development of the
spiritual life of society.
It now remains to elucidate the following question:
what, from the viewpoint of historical materialism, is meant by the “conditions
of material life of society” which in the final analysis determine the
physiognomy of society, its ideas, views, political institutions, etc.?
What, after all, are these “conditions of material
life of society,” what are their distinguishing features?
There can be no doubt that the concept “conditions of
material life of society” includes, first of all, nature which surrounds
society, geographical environment, which is one of the indispensable and
constant conditions of material life of society and which, of course,
influences the development of society. What role does geographical environment
play in the development of society? Is geographical environment the chief force
determining the physiognomy of society, the character of the social system of
men, the transition from one system to another?
Historical materialism answers this question in the
negative.
Geographical environment is unquestionably one of the
constant and indispensable conditions of development of society and, of course,
influences the development of society, accelerates or retards its development.
But its influence is not the determining influence, inasmuch as the
changes and development of society proceed at an incomparably faster rate than
the changes and development of geographical environment. In the space of three
thousand years three different social systems have been successively superseded
in Europe: the primitive communal system, the slave system and the feudal
system. In the eastern part of Europe, in the U.S.S.R., even four social
systems have been superseded. Yet during this period geographical conditions in
Europe have either not changed at all, or have changed so slightly that
geography takes no note of them. And that is quite natural. Changes in geographical
environment of any importance require millions of years, whereas a few hundred
or a couple of thousand years are enough for even very important changes in the
system of human society.
It follows from this that geographical environment
cannot be the chief cause, the determining cause of social development,
for that which remains almost unchanged in the course of tens of thousands of
years cannot be the chief cause of development of that which undergoes
fundamental changes in the course of a few hundred years.
Further, there can be no doubt that the concept
“conditions of material life of society” also includes growth of population,
density of population of one degree or another, for people are an essential
element of the conditions of material life of society, and without a definite
minimum number of people there can be no material life of society. Is not
growth of population the chief force that determines the character of the
social system of man?
Historical materialism answers this question too in
the negative.
Of course, growth of population does influence the
development of society, does facilitate or retard the development of society,
but it cannot be the chief force of development of society, and its influence
on the development of society cannot be the determining influence
because, by itself, growth of population does not furnish the clue to the
question why a given social system is replaced precisely by such and such a new
system and not by another, why the primitive communal system is succeeded precisely
by the slave system, the slave system by the feudal system, and the feudal
system by the bourgeois system, and not by some other.
If growth of population were the determining force of
social development, then a higher density of population would be bound to give
rise to a correspondingly higher type of social system. But we do not find this
to be the case. The density of population in China is four times as great as in
the U.S.A., yet the U.S.A. stands higher than China in the scale of social
development, for in China a semi-feudal system still prevails, whereas the
U.S.A. has long ago reached the highest stage of development of capitalism. The
density of population in Belgium is nineteen times as great as in the U.S.A.,
and twenty-six times as great as in the U.S.S.R. Yet the U.S.A. stands higher
than Belgium in the scale of social development; and as for the U.S.S.R.,
Belgium lags a whole historical epoch behind this country, for in Belgium the
capitalist system prevails, whereas the U.S.S.R. has already done away with
capitalism and has set up a Socialist system.
It follows from this that growth of population is not,
and cannot be, the chief force of development of society, the force which determines
the character of the social system, the physiognomy of society.
What, then, is the chief force in the complex of
conditions of material life of society which determines the physiognomy of
society, the character of the social system, the development of society from
one system to another?
This force, historical materialism holds, is the method
of procuring the means of life necessary for human existence, the mode
of production of material values – food, clothing, footwear, houses, fuel,
instruments of production, etc. – which are indispensable for the life of
development of society.
In order to live, people must have food, clothing,
footwear, shelter, fuel, etc.; in order to have these material values, people
must produce them; and in order to produce them, people must have the
instruments of production with which food, clothing, footwear, shelter, fuel,
etc., are produced; they must be able to produce these instruments and to use
them.
The instruments of production wherewith
material values are produced, the people who operate the instruments of
production and carry on the production of material values thanks to a certain production
experience and labour skill – all these elements jointly constitute
the productive forces of society.
But the productive forces are only one aspect of
production, only one aspect of the mode of production, an aspect that expresses
the relation of men to the objects and forces of nature which they make use of
for the production of material values. Another aspect of production, another aspect
of the mode of production, is the relation of men to each other in the process
of production, men’s relations of production. Men carry on a struggle
against nature and utilize nature for the production of material values not in
isolation from each other, not as separate individuals, but in common, in
groups, in societies. Production, therefore, is at all times and under all
conditions social production. In the production of material values men enter
into mutual relations of one kind or another within production, into relations
of production of one kind or another. These may be relations of co-operation
and mutual help between people who are free from exploitation; they may be
relations of domination and subordination; and, lastly, they may be transitional
from one form of relations of production to another. But whatever the character
of the relations of production may be, always and in every system, they
constitute just as essential an element of production as the productive forces
of society.
“In production,” Marx says, “men not only act on
nature but also on one another. They produce only by co-operating in a certain
way and mutually exchanging their activities. In order to produce, they enter
into definite connections and relations with one another and only within these
social connections and relations does their action on nature, does production,
take place.” (Karl Marx, Selected Works, Vol. I, p. 264.)
Consequently, production, the mode of production,
embraces both the productive forces of society and men’s relations of
production, and is thus the embodiment of their unity in the process of
production of material values.
One of the features of production is that it never stays at one point for a long time and
is always in a state of change and development, and that, furthermore, changes
in the mode of production inevitably call forth changes in the whole social
system, social ideas, political views and political institutions – they call
forth a reconstruction of the whole social and political order. At different
stages of development people make use of different modes of production, or, to
put it more crudely, lead different manners of life. In the primitive commune
there is one mode of production, under slavery there is another mode of
production, under feudalism a third mode of production, and so on. And,
correspondingly, men’s social system, the spiritual life of men, their views
and political institutions also vary.
Whatever is the mode of production of a society, such
in the main is the society itself, its ideas and theories, its political views
and institutions.
Or, to put it more crudely, whatever is man’s manner
of life, such is his manner of thought.
This means that the history of development of society
is above all the history of the development of production, the history of the
modes of production which succeed each other in the course of centuries, the
history of the development of productive forces and people’s relations of
production.
Hence the history of social development is at the same
time the history of the producers of material values themselves, the history of
the labouring masses who are the chief force in the process of production and
who carry on the production of material values necessary for the existence of
society.
Hence, if historical science is to be a real science,
it can no longer reduce the history of social development to the actions of
kings and generals, to the actions of “conquerors” and “subjugators” of states,
but must above all devote itself to the history of the producers of material
values, the history of the labouring masses, the history of peoples.
Hence the clue to the study of the laws of history of
society must not be sought in men’s minds, in the views and ideas of society,
but in the mode of production practised by society in any given historical
period; it must be sought in the economic life of society.
Hence the prime task of historical science is to study
and disclose the laws of production, the laws of development of the productive
forces and of the relations of production, the laws of economic development of
society.
Hence, if the party of the proletariat is to be a real
party, it must above all acquire a knowledge of the laws of development of
production, of the laws of economic development of society.
Hence, if it is not to err in policy, the party of the
proletariat must both in drafting its program and in its practical activities
proceed primarily from the laws of development of production, from the laws of
economic development of society.
A second feature of production is that its changes and development always begin with
changes and development of the productive forces, and, in the first place, with
changes and development of the instruments of production. Productive forces are
therefore the most mobile and revolutionary element of production. First the
productive forces of society change and develop, and then, depending on
these changes and in conformity with them, men’s relations of
production, their economic relations, change. This, however, does not mean that
the relations of production do not influence the development of the productive
forces and that the latter are not dependent on the former. While their
development is dependent on the development of the productive forces, the
relations of production in their turn react upon the development of the
productive forces, accelerating or retarding it. In this connection it should
be noted that the relations of production cannot for too long a time lag behind
and be in a state of contradiction to the growth of the productive forces,
inasmuch as the productive forces can develop in full measure only when the
relations of production correspond to the character, the state of the
productive forces and allow full scope for their development. Therefore,
however much the relations of production may lag behind the development of the
productive forces, they must, sooner or later, come into correspondence with –
and actually do come into correspondence with – the level of development of the
productive forces, the character of the productive forces. Otherwise we would
have a fundamental violation of the unity of the productive forces and the
relations of production within the system of production, a disruption of
production as a whole, a crisis of production, a destruction of productive
forces.
An instance in which the relations of production do
not correspond to the character of the productive forces, conflict with them,
is the economic crises in capitalist countries, where private capitalist
ownership of the means of production is in glaring incongruity with the social
character of the process of production, with the character of the productive
forces. This results in economic crises, which lead to the destruction of
productive forces. Furthermore, this incongruity itself constitutes the
economic basis of social revolution, the purpose of which is to destroy the
existing relations of production and to create new relations of production
corresponding to the character of the productive forces.
In contrast, an instance in which the relations of
production completely correspond to the character of the productive forces is
the Socialist national economy of the U.S.S.R., where the social ownership of
the means of production fully corresponds to the social character of the
process of production, and where, because of this, economic crises and the
destruction of productive forces are unknown.
Consequently, the productive forces are not only the
most mobile and revolutionary element in production, but are also the
determining element in the development of production.
Whatever are the productive forces such must be the
relations of production
While the state of the productive forces furnishes an
answer to the question – with what instruments of production do men produce the
material values they need? – the state of the relations of production furnishes
the answer to another question – who owns the means of production (the
land, forests, waters, mineral resources, raw materials, instruments of
production, production premises, means of transportation and communication,
etc.), who commands the means of production, whether the whole of society, or
individual persons, groups, or classes which utilize them for the exploitation
of other persons, groups or classes?
Here is a rough picture of the development of
productive forces from ancient times to our day. The transition from crude
stone tools to the bow and arrow, and the accompanying transition from the life
of hunters to the domestication of animals and primitive pasturage; the
transition from stone tools to metal tools (the iron axe, the wooden plough
fitted with an iron colter, etc.), with a corresponding transition to tillage
and agriculture; a further improvement in metal tools for the working up of
materials, the introduction of the blacksmith’s bellows, the introduction of
pottery, with a corresponding development of handicrafts, the separation of
handicrafts from agriculture, the development of an independent handicraft
industry and, subsequently, of manufacture; the transition from handicraft
tools to machines and the transformation of handicraft and manufacture into
machine industry; the transition to the machine system and the rise of modern
large-scale machine industry – such is a general and far from complete picture
of the development of the productive forces of society in the course of man’s
history. It will be clear that the development and improvement of the
instruments of production were effected by men who were related to production,
and not independently of men; and, consequently, the change and development of
the instruments of production were accompanied by a change and development of
men, as the most important element of the productive forces, by a change and
development of their production experience, their labour skill, their ability
to handle the instruments of production.
In conformity with the change and development of the
productive forces of society in the course of history, men’s relations of
production, their economic relations also changed and developed.
Five main types of relations of production are
known to history: primitive communal, slave, feudal, capitalist and Socialist.
The basis of the relations of production under the
primitive communal system is that the means of production are socially owned.
This in the main corresponds to the character of the productive forces of that
period. Stone tools, and, later, the bow and arrow, precluded the possibility
of men individually combating the forces of nature and beasts of prey. In order
to gather the fruits of the forest, to catch fish, to build some sort of
habitation, men were obliged to work in common if they did not want to die of
starvation, or fall victim to beasts of prey or to neighbouring societies.
Labour in common led to the common ownership of the means of production, as
well as of the fruits of production. Here the conception of private ownership
of the means of production did not yet exist, except for the personal ownership
of certain implements of production which were at the same time means of
defence against beasts of prey. Here there was no exploitation, no classes.
The basis of the relations of production under the
slave system is that the slave owner owns the means of production; he also owns
the worker in production – the slave, whom he can sell, purchase, or kill as
though he were an animal. Such relations of production in the main correspond
to the state of the productive forces of that period. Instead of stone tools,
men now have metal tools at their command; instead of the wretched and primitive
husbandry of the hunter, who knew neither pasturage, nor tillage, there now
appear pasturage, tillage, handicrafts, and a division of labour between these
branches of production. There appears the possibility of the exchange of
products between individuals and between societies, of the accumulation of
wealth in the hands of a few, the actual accumulation of the means of
production in the hands of a minority, and the possibility of subjugation of
the majority by a minority and their conversion into slaves. Here we no longer
find the common and free labour of all members of society in the production
process – here there prevails the forced labour of slaves, who are exploited by
the non-labouring slave owners. Here, therefore, there is no common ownership of
the means of production or of the fruits of production. It is replaced by
private ownership. Here the slave owner appears as the prime and principal
property owner in the full sense of the term.
Rich and poor, exploiters and exploited, people with
full rights and people with no rights, and a fierce class struggle between them
– such is the picture of the slave system.
The basis of the relations of
production under the feudal system is that the feudal lord owns the means of
production and does not fully own the worker in production – the serf, whom the
feudal lord can no longer kill, but whom he can buy and sell. Alongside of
feudal ownership there exists individual ownership by the peasant and the
handicraftsman of his implements of production and his private enterprise based
on his personal labour. Such relations of production in the main correspond to
the state of the productive forces of that period. Further improvements in the
smelting and working of iron; the spread of the iron plough and the loom; the further
development of agriculture, horticulture, viniculture and dairying; the
appearance of manufactories alongside of the handicraft workshops – such are
the characteristic features of the state of the productive forces.
The new productive forces demand that the labourer
shall display some kind of initiative in production and an inclination for
work, an interest in work. The feudal lord therefore discards the slave, as a
labourer who has no interest in work and is entirely without initiative, and
prefers to deal with the serf, who has his own husbandry, implements of
production, and a certain interest in work essential for the cultivation of the
land and for the payment in kind of a part of his harvest to the feudal lord.
Here private ownership is further developed.
Exploitation is nearly as severe as it was under slavery – it is only slightly
mitigated. A class struggle between exploiters and exploited is the principal
feature of the feudal system.
The basis of the relations of production under the
capitalist system is that the capitalist owns the means of production, but not
the workers in production – the wage labourers, whom the capitalist can neither
kill nor sell because they are personally free, but who are deprived of means
of production and, in order not to die of hunger, are obliged to sell their
labour power to the capitalist and to bear the yoke of exploitation. Alongside
of capitalist property in the means of production, we find, at first on a wide
scale, private property of the peasants and handicraftsmen in the means of
production, these peasants and handicraftsmen no longer being serfs, and their
private property being based on personal labour. In place of the handicraft
workshops and manufactories there appear huge mills and factories equipped with
machinery. In place of the manorial estates tilled by the primitive implements
of production of the peasant, there now appear large capitalist farms run on
scientific lines and supplied with agricultural machinery.
The new productive forces require that the workers in
production shall be better educated and more intelligent than the downtrodden
and ignorant serfs, that they be able to understand machinery and operate it
properly. Therefore, the capitalists prefer to deal with wage workers who are
free from the bonds of serfdom and who are educated enough to be able properly
to operate machinery.
But having developed productive forces to a tremendous
extent, capitalism has become enmeshed in contradictions which it is unable to
solve. By producing larger and larger quantities of commodities, and reducing
their prices, capitalism intensifies competition, ruins the mass of small and
medium private owners, converts them into proletarians and reduces their
purchasing power, with the result that it becomes impossible to dispose of the
commodities produced. On the other hand, by expanding production and
concentrating millions of workers in huge mills and factories, capitalism lends
the process of production a social character and thus undermines its own foundation,
inasmuch as the social character of the process of production demands the
social ownership of the means of production; yet the means of production remain
private capitalist property, which is incompatible with the social character of
the process of production.
These irreconcilable contradictions between the
character of the productive forces and the relations of production make
themselves felt in periodical crises of overproduction, when the capitalists,
finding no effective demand for their goods owing to the ruin of the mass of
the population which they themselves have brought about, are compelled to burn
products, destroy manufactured goods, suspend production, and destroy
productive forces at a time when millions of people are forced to suffer unemployment
and starvation, not because there are not enough goods, but because there is an
overproduction of goods.
This means that the capitalist relations of production
have ceased to correspond to the state of productive forces of society and have
come into irreconcilable contradiction with them.
This means that capitalism is pregnant with
revolution, whose mission it is to replace the existing capitalist ownership of
the means of production by Socialist ownership.
This means that the main feature of the capitalist
system is a most acute class struggle between the exploiters and the exploited.
The basis of the relations of production under the
Socialist system, which so far has been established only in the U.S.S.R., is
the social ownership of the means of production. Here there are no longer
exploiters and exploited. The goods produced are distributed according to
labour performed, on the principle: “He who does not work, neither shall he
eat.” Here the mutual relations of people in the process of production are
marked by comradely co-operation and the Socialist mutual assistance of workers
who are free from exploitation. Here the relations of production fully
correspond to the state of productive forces, for the social character of the
process of production is reinforced by the social ownership of the means of
production.
For this reason Socialist production
in the U.S.S.R. knows no periodical crises of overproduction and their
accompanying absurdities.
For this reason, the productive forces here develop at
an accelerated pace, for the relations of production that correspond to them
offer full scope for such development.
Such is the picture of the development of men’s
relations of production in the course of human history.
Such is the dependence of the development of the
relations of production on the development of the production forces of society,
and primarily, on the development of the instruments of production, the
dependence by virtue of which the changes and development of the productive
forces sooner or later lead to corresponding changes and development of the
relations of production.
“The use and fabrication of
instruments of labour,”[1]
says Marx, “although existing in the germ among certain species of animals, is
specifically characteristic of the human labour-process, and Franklin therefore
defines man as a tool-making animal. Relics of bygone instruments of labour
possess the same importance for the investigation of extinct economic forms of
society, as do fossil bones for the determination of extinct species of
animals. It is not the articles made, but how they are made, and by what
instruments that enables us to distinguish different economic epochs....
Instruments of labour not only supply a standard of the degree of development
to which human labour has attained but they are also indicators of the social
conditions under which that labour is carried on.” (Karl Marx, Capital,
Vol. I, p, 159.)
And further:
a) “Social relations are closely bound up with
productive forces. In acquiring new productive forces men change their mode of
production; and in changing their mode of production, in changing the way of
earning their living, they change all their social conditions. The hand-mill
gives you society with the feudal lord; the steam-mill, society with the
industrial capitalist.” (Karl Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy, p. 92.)
b) “There is a continual movement of growth in
productive forces, of destruction in social relations, of formation in ideas;
the only immutable thing is the abstraction of movement.” (Ibid., p.
93.)
Speaking of historical materialism as formulated in The
Communist Manifesto, Engels says:
“Economic production and the structure of society of
every historical epoch necessarily arising therefrom constitute the foundation
for the political and intellectual history of that epoch;... consequently ever
since the dissolution of the primeval communal ownership of land all history
has been a history of class struggles, of struggles between exploited and
exploiting, between dominated and dominating classes at various stages of
social evolution;... this struggle, however, has now reached a stage where the
exploited and oppressed class (the proletariat) can no longer emancipate itself
from the class which exploits and oppresses it (the bourgeoisie), without at
the same time forever freeing the whole of society from exploitation,
oppression and class struggles.” (Preface to the German edition of The
Communist Manifesto – Karl Marx, Selected Works, Vol. I, pp. 192-93.)
A third feature of production is that the rise of new productive forces and of the
relations of production corresponding to them does not take place separately
from the old system, after the disappearance of the old system, but within the
old system; it takes place not as a result of the deliberate and conscious
activity of man, but spontaneously, unconsciously, independently of the will of
man. It takes place spontaneously and independently of the will of man for two
reasons.
First, because men are not free to choose one mode of
production or another, because as every new generation enters life it finds
productive forces and relations of production already existing as the result of
the work of former generations, owing to which it is obliged at first to accept
and adapt itself to everything it finds ready made in the sphere of production
in order to be able to produce material values.
Secondly, because, when improving one instrument of
production or another, one element of the productive forces or another, men do
not realize, do not understand or stop to reflect what social results
these improvements will lead to, but only think of their everyday interests, of
lightening their labour and of securing some direct and tangible advantage for
themselves.
When, gradually and gropingly, certain members of
primitive communal society passed from the use of stone tools to the use of
iron tools, they, of course, did not know and did not stop to reflect what social
results this innovation would lead to; they did not understand or realize that
the change to metal tools meant a revolution in production, that it would in
the long run lead to the slave system. They simply wanted to lighten their
labour and secure an immediate and tangible advantage; their conscious activity
was confined within the narrow bounds of this everyday personal interest.
When, in the period of the feudal system, the young
bourgeoisie of Europe began to erect, alongside of the small guild workshops,
large manufactories, and thus advanced the productive forces of society, it, of
course, did not know and did not stop to reflect what social consequences
this innovation would lead to; it did not realize or understand that this
“small” innovation would lead to a regrouping of social forces which was to end
in a revolution both against the power of kings, whose favours it so highly
valued, and against the nobility, to whose ranks its foremost representatives
not infrequently aspired. It simply wanted to lower the cost of producing
goods, to throw large quantities of goods on the markets of Asia and of
recently discovered America, and to make bigger profits. Its conscious activity
was confined within the narrow bounds of this commonplace practical aim.
When the Russian capitalists, in conjunction with
foreign capitalists, energetically implanted modern large-scale machine
industry in Russia, while leaving tsardom intact and turning the peasants over
to the tender mercies of the landlords, they, of course, did not know and did
not stop to reflect what social consequences this extensive growth of
productive forces would lead to, they did not realize or understand that this
big leap in the realm of the productive forces of society would lead to a
regrouping of social forces that would enable the proletariat to effect a union
with the peasantry and to bring about a victorious Socialist revolution. They
simply wanted to expand industrial production to the limit, to gain control of
the huge home market, to become monopolists, and to squeeze as much profit as
possible out of the national economy. Their conscious activity did not extend
beyond their commonplace, strictly practical interests. Accordingly, Marx says:
“In the social production which men carry on (that is,
in the production of the material values necessary to the life of men – Ed.)
they enter into definite relations that are indispensable and independent[2] of
their will; these relations of production correspond to a definite stage of
development of their material forces of production.” (Karl Marx, Selected
Works, Vol. I, p. 356.)
This, however, does not mean that changes in the
relations of production, and the transition from old relations of production to
new relations of production proceed smoothly, without conflicts, without
upheavals. On the contrary, such a transition usually takes place by means of
the revolutionary overthrow of the old relations of production and the
establishment of new relations of production. Up to a certain period the
development of the productive forces and the changes in the realm of the
relations of production proceed spontaneously, independently of the will of
men. But that is so only up to a certain moment, until the new and developing
productive forces have reached a proper state of maturity. After the new
productive forces have matured, the existing relations of production and their
upholders – the ruling classes – become that “insuperable” obstacle which can
only be removed by the conscious action of the new classes, by the forcible
acts of these classes, by revolution. Here there stands out in bold relief the tremendous
role of new social ideas, of new political institutions, of a new political
power, whose mission it is to abolish by force the old relations of production.
Out of the conflict between the new productive forces and the old relations of
production, out of the new economic demands of society there arise new social
ideas; the new ideas organize and mobilize the masses; the masses become welded
into a new political army, create a new revolutionary power, and make use of it
to abolish by force the old system of relations of production, and firmly to
establish the new system. The spontaneous process of development yields place
to the conscious actions of men, peaceful development to violent upheaval,
evolution to revolution.
“The proletariat,” says Marx, “during its contest with
the bourgeoisie is compelled, by the force of circumstances, to organize itself
as a class... by means of a revolution, it makes itself the ruling class, and,
as such, sweeps away by force the old conditions of production.” (The
Communist Manifesto – Karl Marx, Selected Works, Vol. I, p. 228.)
And further:
a) “The proletariat will use its political supremacy
to wrest, by degrees, all capital from the bourgeoisie, to centralize all
instruments of production in the hands of the state, i.e., of the
proletariat organized as the ruling class; and to increase the total of
productive forces as rapidly as possible.” (Ibid., p. 227.)
b) “Force is the midwife of every old society pregnant
with a new one.” (Karl Marx, Capital, Vol. I, p. 776.)
Here is the brilliant formulation of the essence of
historical materialism given by Marx in 1859 in his historic Preface to his
famous book, Critique of Political Economy:
“In the social production which
men carry on they enter into definite relations that are indispensable and
independent of their will; these relations of production correspond to a
definite stage of development of their material forces of production. The sum
total of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of
society – the real foundation, on which rises a legal and political
superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness.
The mode of production in material life determines the social, political and
intellectual life process in general. It is not the consciousness of men that determines
their being, but, on the contrary, their social being that determines their
consciousness. At a certain stage of their development, the material forces of
production in society come in conflict with the existing relations of
production, or – what is but a legal expression for the same thing – with the
property relations within which they have been at work before. From forms of
development of the forces of production these relations turn into their
fetters. Then begins an epoch of social revolution. With the change of the
economic foundation the entire immense superstructure is more or less rapidly
transformed. In considering such transformations a distinction should always be
made between the material transformation of the economic conditions of production
which can be determined with the precision of natural science, and the legal,
political, religious, esthetic or philosophic – in short, ideological forms in
which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out. Just as our
opinion of an individual is not based on what he thinks of himself, so can we
not judge of such a period of transformation by its own consciousness; on the
contrary, this consciousness must be explained rather from the contradictions
of material life, from the existing conflict between the social forces of
production and the relations of production. No social order ever disappears
before all the productive forces for which there is room in it have been
developed; and new higher relations of production never appear before the
material conditions of their existence have matured in the womb of the old
society itself. Therefore, mankind always sets itself only such tasks as it can
solve; since, looking at the matter more closely, we will always find that the
task itself arises only when the material conditions necessary for its solution
already exists or are at least in the process of formation.” (Karl Marx, Selected
Works, Vol. I, pp. 356-57.)
Such is Marxist materialism as applied to social life,
to the history of society.
Such are the principal features of dialectical and
historical materialism.
It will be seen from this what a theoretical treasure
was safeguarded by Lenin for the Party and protected from the attacks of the
revisionists and renegades, and how important was the appearance of Lenin’s
book, Materialism and Empirio-Criticism, for the development of our
Party.
Reprinted from: History of the
Communist Party of the Soviet Union (Bolsheviks)
Short Course
Chapter Four, Section 2
Communist Party of the Soviet Union (Bolsheviks)
Short Course
Chapter Four, Section 2
Red Star Publishers
www.RedStarPublishers.org
www.RedStarPublishers.org
[1] By instruments of labour Marx has in mind primarily instruments of
production – Ed.
[2] Our italics – Ed.
Aucun commentaire:
Enregistrer un commentaire